The hypothesis
In a recent handout, I discuss the following hypothesis, implicit in my dissertation (Gorman 2013):
(1) Alternation Phonotactic Hypothesis: Let A, B, C, and D be (possibly-null) string sets. Then, if a grammar G contains a surface-true rule of alternation A → B / C __ D, nonce words containing the subsequence CAD are ill-formed for speakers of G.
Before I continue, note that definition is “phenomenological” in the sense that refers to two notions—alternations and surface-true-ness—which are not generally considered to be encoded directly in the grammar. Regarding the notion of alternations, it is not difficult to formalize whether or not a rule is alternating.
(2) Let a rule be defined by possibly-null string sets A, B, C, and D as in (1). Then if any elements of B are phonemes, then the rule is a rule of alternation.
(3) [ditto] If no elements of B are phonemes, then the rule is a rule of (pure) allophony.
But from the argument against bi-uniqueness in Sound Pattern of Russian (Halle 1959), it follows that we should reject a grammar-internal distinction between rules of alternation and allophony, and subsequent theory provides no way to encode this distinction in the grammar. Similarly, it is not hard to define what it means for a rule to be surface-true.
(4) [ditto] If no instances of CAD are generated by the grammar G, then the rule is surface-true.
But, there does not seem to be much reason for that notion to be encoded in the grammar and the theory does not provide any way to encode it.1 Note further that I am also deliberately stating in (1) that a constraint against CAD has been “projected” from the alternation, rather than treating such constraints as autonomous entities of the theory as is done in Optimality Theory (OT) and friends. Finally, I have phrased this in terms of grammaticality (“are ill-formed”) rather than acceptability.
Why might the Alternation Phonotactic Hypothesis (henceforth, APH) be true? First, I take it as obvious that alternations are more entrenched facts about grammars than pure allophony. For instance, in English, stop aspiration could be governed by a rule of allophony, but it is also plausible that English speakers simply represent aspirated stops as such in their lexical entries since there are no aspiration alternations. This point was made separately by Dell (1973) and Stampe (1973), and motivates the notion of lexicon optimization in OT. In contrast, though, rules of alternation (or someting like them) are actually necessary to obtain the proper surface forms. An English speaker who does not have a rule of obstruent voice assimilation will simply not produce the right allomorphs of various affixes. In contrast, the same speaker need not encode a process of nasalization—which in English is clearly allophonic (see, e.g., Kager 1999: 31f.)—to obtain the correct outputs. Given that alternations are entrenched in the relevant sense, it is not impossible to imagine that speakers might “project” constraints out of alternation generalizations in the manner described above. Such constraints could be used during online processing, assuming a strong isomorphism between grammatical representations used during production and perception.2 Secondly, since not all alternations are surface-true, it seems reasonable to limit this process of projection to those which are. Were one to project non-surface-true constraints in this fashion, the speaker would find themselves in an awkward position in which actual words are ill-formed.3,4
The APH is interesting contrasted with the following:
(5) Lexicostatistic Phonotactic Hypothesis: Let A, C, and D be (possibly-null) string sets. Then, if CAD is statistically underrepresented (in a sense to be determined) in the lexicon L of a grammar G, nonce words containing the subsequence CAD are ill-formed for speakers of G.
According to the LSPH (as we’ll call it), phonotactic knowledge is projected not from alternations but from statistical analysis of the lexicon. The LSPH is at least implicit in the robust cottage industry which uses statistical and/or computational modeling of the lexicon to infer the existence of phonotactic generalizations. It is notable how virtually none of the “cottage industry” of LSPH work discusses anything like the APH. Finally, one should note that APH and the LSPH do not exhaust the set of possibilities. For instance, Berent et al. (2007) and Daland et al. (2011) test for effects of the Sonority Sequencing Principle, a putative linguistic universal, on wordlikeness judgments. And some have denied the mere existence of phonotactic constraints.
Gorman 2013 reviews some prior results which argue in favor of the APH, which I’ll describe below.
Consider the putative English phonotactic constraint *V̄ʃ#, a constraint against word-final sequences of tense vowels followed by [ʃ] proposed by Iverson & Salmons (2005). Exceptions to this generalization tend to be markedly foreign (e.g., cartouche), to be proper names (e.g., LaRouche), or to convey an “affective, onomatopoeic quality” (e.g., sheesh, woosh). As Gorman (2013:43f.) notes, this constraint is statistically robust, but Hayes & White (2013) report that it has no measurable effect on English speakers’ wordlikeness judgments. In contrast, three English alternation rules (nasal place assimilation, obstruent voice assimilation, and degemination) have a substantial impact on wordlikeness judgments (Gorman 2013, ch. 4).
A secod, more elaborate example comes from Turkish. Lees (1966a,b) proposes three phonotactic constraints in this language: backness harmony, roundness harmony, and labial attraction. All three of these constraints have exceptions, but Gorman (p. 57-60) shows that they are statistically robust generalizations. Thus, under the LSPH, speakers ought to be sensitive to all three.
Endnotes
- I note that the CONTROL module proposed by Orgun & Sprouse (1999) might be a mechanism by which this information could be encoded.
- Some evidence that phonotactic knowledge is deployed in production comes from the study of Finnish and Turkish, both of which have robust vowel harmony. Suomi et al. (1997) and Vroomen et al. (1998) find that disharmony seemingly acts as a cue for word boundaries in Finnish, and Kabak et al. (2010) find something similar for Turkish, but not in French, which lacks harmony.
- Durvasula & Kahng (2019) find that speakers do not necessarily judge a nonce word to be ill-formed just because it fails to follow certain subtle allophonic generalizations, which suggests that the distinction between allophony and alternation may be important here.
- I note that it has sometimes been proposed that actual words of G may in fact be gradiently marked or otherwise degraded w.r.t. to grammar G if they violate phonotactic constraints projected from G (e.g., Coetzee 2008). However, the null hypothesis, it seems to me, is that all actual words are also possible words and so it does not make sense to speak of actual words as marked or ill-formed, gradiently or otherwise.
References
Berent, I., Steriade, D., Lennertz, T., and Vaknin, V. 2007. What we know about what we have never heard: evidence from perceptual illusions. Cognition 104: 591-630.
Coetzee, A. W. 2008. Grammaticality and ungrammaticality in phonology. Language 64(2): 218-257. [I critique this briefly in Gorman 2013, p. 4f.]
Daland, R., Hayes, B., White, J., Garellek, M., Davis, A., and Norrmann, I. 2011. Explaining sonority projection effects. Phonology 28: 197-234.
Dell, F. 1973. Les règles et les sons. Hermann.
Durvasula, K. and Kahng, J. 2019. Phonological acceptability is not isomorphic with phonological grammaticality of stimulus. Talk presented at the Annual Meeting on Phonology.
Gorman, K. 2013. Generative phonotactics. Doctoral dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.
Halle, M. 1959. Sound Pattern of Russian. Mouton.
Hayes, B. and White, J. 2013. Phonological naturalness and phonotactic learning. Linguistic Inquiry 44: 45-75.
Iverson, G. K. and Salmons, J. C. 2005. Filling the gap: English tense vowel plus final
/š/. Journal of English Linguistics 33: 1-15.
Kager, R. 1999. Optimality Theory. Cambridge University Press.
Orgun, C. O. and Sprouse, R. 1999. From MPARSE to CONTROL: deriving ungrammaticality. Phonology 16: 191-224.
Kabak, B., Maniwa, K., and Kazanina, N. 2010. Listeners use vowel harmony and word-final stress to spot nonsense words: a study of Turkish and French. Journal of Laboratory Phonology 1: 207-224.
Lees, R. B. 1966a. On the interpretation of a Turkish vowel alternation. Anthropological Linguistics 8: 32-39.
Lees, R. B. 1966b. Turkish harmony and the description of assimilation. Türk Dili
Araştırmaları Yıllığı Belletene 1966: 279-297
Stampe, D. 1973. A Dissertation on Natural Phonology. Garland. [I don’t have this in front of me but if I remember correctly, Stampe argues non-surface true phonological rules are essentially second-class citizens.]
Suomi, K. McQueen, J. M., and Cutler, A. 1997. Vowel harmony and speech segmentation in Finnish. Journal of Memory and Language 36: 422-444.
Vroomen, J., Tuomainen, J. and de Gelder, B. 1998. The roles of word stress and vowel harmony in speech segmentation. Journal of Memory and Language 38: 133-149.
See Caitlin Richter’s dissertation which I think answers a lot of fundamental problems in how phonological representations arise from phonetic representations.
https://www.ling.upenn.edu/~ricca/dissertation/richter_2021.pdf